A little more than a week ago I posted an article here about a book by John Carey - "What Good Are Arts?" in which the author questions the value/ futility of defining "art". Carey surmises that the definition of good or bad art is best left to the consumer until there is a scientific yardstick to measure what indeed constitutes an artistic experience. ( The blog post generated a lively discussion between me and a reader.)
Here is a follow up to the previous post explaining the "scientific basis" of art. Researcher and neuroscientist, V.S. Ramachandran of the University of California, San Diego declares that while 90% of art is culture driven (put that in the category of "art history /appreciation), 10% is universal human reaction rooted in the brain. Ramachandran discussed the biological rationale of art on BBC's Reith Lectures series on The Emerging Mind. If you have the time and the inclination, read about his views on The Artful Brain here.
".. I'd like to take up one of the most ancient questions in philosophy, psychology and anthropology, namely what is art? When Picasso said: "Art is the lie that reveals the truth" what exactly did he mean? In particular what I'd like to do is raise the question: "Are there such things as artistic universals?"
When I speak of artistic universals I am not denying the enormous role played by culture. Obviously culture plays a tremendous role, otherwise you wouldn't have different artistic styles - but it doesn't follow that art is completely idiosyncratic and arbitrary either or that there are no universal laws.
Let me put it somewhat differently. Let's assume that 90% of the variance you see in art is driven by cultural diversity or - more cynically - by just the auctioneer's hammer, and only 10% by universal laws that are common to all brains. The culturally driven 90% is what most people already study - it's called art history. As a scientist what I am interested in is the 10% that is universal - not in the endless variations imposed by cultures. The advantage that I and other scientists have today is that unlike we can now test our conjectures by directly studying the brain empirically. There's even a new name for this discipline. My colleague Semir Zeki calls it Neuro-aesthetics - just to annoy the philosophers."
I love the new name for this discipline and hope to take this topic up also at www.brainbasedbusiness.com where we also bring together the experts in ways that help people use these great ideas to improve their situation. Thanks for the innovative suggestions here!
Posted by: Ellen | April 19, 2006 at 06:57 AM
Ellen:
I was quite fascinated by Ramachandran pin-pointing a particular area of the brain - the "right parietal," as the region of artistic activity and by his claim that the brain recognizes metaphorical and hyper-distorted images of real objects as "art"
What practical application do you see for Neuro-aesthetics?
Posted by: Ruchira Paul | April 19, 2006 at 02:47 PM
What a great question -- because I sense there are some amazing applications and since that is what I do, Ruchira, I'll think -- talk to others and get back.
Posted by: Ellen | April 19, 2006 at 04:31 PM
Ruchira may already suspect that I'm lurking, but I can't keep quiet here. "What practical application...?" Precisely. It is a practical enterprise, this neuro-aesthetics (NA), which means it will serve practical ends. So when a skeptic like John Hyman writes, "I want to discuss a new area of scientific research called neuro-aesthetics, which is the study of art by neuroscientists," he is probably deliberately (for his antagonistic purporses) misrepresenting what such a study can or will do. Neuroscientists do not study art. They study brain activity. To the extent that "what art really is" can be so localized and specified in terms of brain activity, NA would have much to offer. But it won't have told us much about art, which after all has its social and material aspects, too. It will have told us something about a neurological component of art appreciation. The very framing of the query--"what art really is"--gives away the "real" nature of NA. What if art isn't really one thing or another?
Posted by: Dean C. Rowan | April 19, 2006 at 06:47 PM
Dean, thanks for lurking and for linking to the very interesting riposte by John Hyman.
Hyman raises some legitimate objections to Ramachandran and Zeki's narrow and perhaps self serving (to fit the observable data) definitions of art. I have not much to say here except what I already said in the comments thread of the earlier post - that neuroscience may well be capable of accurately detecting and recording an *aesthetic event* in the brain, but it will be a stretch to say that it will one day be able to accurately or comprehensively define *art*.
Hyman should have raised and supported his objections and let it go at that. Instead, he falls into the trap of his own orthodoxy when he goes on to tell us that the etching by Rembrandt is superior to the one by Carracci, and why.(It is irrelevant that I agree.) He need not have pointed his meticulous fingers at every curve and rumple in that delicious woodcut by Utamaro, instead of leaving it to us to savor (or pan) it. And from what authority does Hyman claim to know whether John Donne's erotic experience did or did not include his fingers straying between his lover's teeth?
Hyman harrumphs with displeasure that according to the scientists, neurological responses to MacDonald and Haagen Dasz could conceivably be in the same category as those triggered by Picasso and Cezanne. Why not? Just because he himself makes a supercilious intellectual distinction between one physiological response and another, it does not necessarily mean that there is one in the realm of the neural network. He can argue about the relative value of enjoying a hamburger and admiring a painting in our everyday cultural and social milieu but to a neuroscientist, the qualitative difference in the pleasure perception of the two in the brain may not be monumental.
So to end, I reiterate what I have said before. Let the scientists not overreach by trying to define art with a formula and a brain scan and the art mavens need not turn up their noses at what constitutes kitsch in their estimation and pure joy to someone else. I am with John Carey on this one.
Posted by: Ruchira Paul | April 19, 2006 at 11:25 PM
Ruchira: I disagree that Hyman needn't have gone on about why the Rembrandt wins. He explains that "part of the business of criticism is [to] make these hard decisions, and to back them with convincing reasons." Is this tantamount to turning up one's nose? Not necessarily, and Hyman's perhaps fulsome descriptions at least provide material to which someone who has not been convinced can target a response.
I also think there's more going on here than the mere measurement and comparison of a category of brain activities. It's one thing for a neuroscientist to delimit such a category and proceed to demonstrate that burger responses are identical to Picasso responses. It's entirely another to dress up this exercise as a more precise, meaningful version of art criticism than, say, Hyman's.
I am in many respects a quietist, for better or worse. Here, however, I disagree that we are better served by silently tolerating each other's estimation as to what is a source of aesthetic pleasure.
Posted by: Dean C. Rowan | April 20, 2006 at 11:29 AM
Dean, you and I are focusing on two different aspects of art appreciation.
From an academic point of view, Hyman is doing his job well - in criticizing the Rembrandt vs Carracci etchings and backing it up with his reasons. For teachers, students, enthusiasts and the discipline of art (or literature) this is a valid (and valuable) exercise. This constitutes that 90% of the "learnt" aesthetics which Ramachandran alluded to. Which is why the Victorian British prude found the voluptuous Indian goddess figure so repulsive and why most Indians familiar with the goddess myth, find her utterly charming. Take for example the similes and metaphors used in ancient Indian mythology to describe a beautiful woman. Her eyes are like a "swarm of bumblebees" or like a "lotus flower" alluding to the dark color of the former and the size of the latter. Her legs are like "a banana tree" drawing upon the comparable smoothness of both. Indians readily understand what the poet refers to. Westerners will probably fall off their chairs laughing ... unless they too have studied and understood that line of beauty appreciation. Many decades ago, a reigning Miss World or Miss Universe, a blonde, was on a goodwill visit to an African country, I forget which one. The local women who had gathered to greet her were told that she was the most beautiful woman in the world. They asked politely what could be so beautiful about a woman who sported a lion's mane on her head.
My own concern here was that intangible (or perhaps the *more* tangible at a scientific level) 10%, which Ramachandran and Zeki claim is the universal visceral response to art. I do not know if we have one - whether all of it is not culture driven. My point is that we will never find out as long as Hyman and other wise men keep telling us what is beautiful. I would love to see a study of neuro-aesthetics free of cultural influences. But that will probably not be ever possible because all pleasure perception will be linked to our prior experience - even in the most naive savage. But there must be an *instinct* for art /aesthetics, be it visual, sensual or some primitive memory driven exercise of communication. Or else, not so many of us would be so enthralled by it.
Posted by: Ruchira Paul | April 20, 2006 at 03:07 PM
It's time for areful thinkers like you Ruchira to brings these ideas into the workplace! and you ARE -- THANKS...
http://www.brainbasedbusiness.com”>Brain Based Business
Posted by: ellenweber | May 31, 2006 at 08:44 AM
Another author who has written vastly on this subject, albeit from an evolutionist's point of view, is Ellen Dissanayake. I read her "What is Art For" a few years ago and found it to be a fascinating read.
Posted by: Masale.Wallah | May 31, 2006 at 10:02 AM